|
go
to homepage go
to updates
Superposition
by
Miles Mathis

Where
the master has failed
What
hope for the student
Had he
obeyed him in all?
—Richard
Wagner, Siegfried
First
posted October 17, 2005
In this paper
I will offer a simple mechanical explanation of superposition. I
will provide an easy visualization as well, one that
simultaneously solves the mystery of superposition and the wave
motion of particles.
Heisenberg
and Bohr assured everyone that this was not possible. The
Copenhagen interpretation, which is still the preferred
interpretation of quantum mechanics by contemporary physicists,
states in no uncertain terms that the mysteries of quantum
physics are categorically unsolvable. That is, they are not only
unsolved, they are impossible to solve. All other interpretations
of quantum mechanics have agreed with this interpretation,
regarding the impossibility of a straightforward visualization or
of a simple mechanical solution. Some variations have denied
other aspects of the Copenhagen interpretation, especially
regarding its opinion of the collapse of the wave function. Bohm,
for instance, has attempted a deterministic explanation of
certain parts of QED, including a reinterpretation of the wave
function and of the Uncertainty Principle. But not even Bohm or
Bell believed that anyone could offer a simple visualization that
would explain superposition or the so-called wave-particle
duality.
Einstein came
closest to this belief. He remained convinced that quantum
mechanics would eventually be explained in a more consistent
manner. But, again, it was mainly the probabilistic nature of
quantum dynamics that bothered him, not the fact that it could
not yield to simple visualizations. He did not like God playing
dice, but he did not expect God to draw us a picture with every
new theory.
I did not
approach the problem intending to find a visualization or an easy
mechanical solution. I only wanted to make better sense of it in
my own mind. But in analyzing the problem I found that the
mechanical difficulties were not nearly as formidable as has been
claimed. I found that I could quite easily visualize the physical
motions, and that I could put these visualizations into pretty
simple words and pictures. One basic discovery allowed me to do
this, and that is what this paper is about.
I believe
that the most efficient way to lead the reader through the
problem is to analyze the current explanation of superposition,
as it is presented in a contemporary text. As my text I will use
David Albert’s Quantum
Mechanics and Experience.
I choose this book for the same reason that the status
quo chose to
publish it: it puts the theory in as clear a form as possible,
for laymen and physicists alike. Albert is a philosophy professor
at Columbia, but he has been embraced and tutored by many
mainstream physicists. This book may therefore be taken as a
representative, if not perfect, expression of current theory. If
it were not it surely would not have been published by Harvard
University Press.
Albert begins
by taking two measurable qualities of an electron. He tells us
that the qualities don’t matter, and that we could call them
color and hardness if we wanted to. In a footnote on page 1 he
informs the reader that experimentally he is talking about x-spin
and y-spin, but he does not elaborate beyond that. Conveniently,
this footnote allows me to make my first major substantive point.
From a logical point of view, an electron cannot have angular
momentum on the x and y axis at the same time—not if both spins
are about an axis through the center (Albert claims that they
are). Imagine the Earth spinning about its axis. Call that axis
the x-axis. Now go to the y-axis, which also goes through the
center but is at a 90o
angle from the x-axis. Try to
imagine spinning the Earth around that axis at the same time that
it is spinning around the x-axis. If you can imagine it, then you
have a very vivid imagination, to say the least.*
To see what I
mean, remember the gyroscope and the phenomenon called
precession. A torque applied to the axis of rotation is
deflected, so that circular motion is not allowed about the
y-axis. You can have circular motion in only one of the two
planes at a time. To see why this is so, think of a point on the
surface of the sphere or on the edge of a wheel. Give it spin in
the xy-plane. Now follow its course and see the curve it
describes. Once you have done that, think of giving it a spin in
the zy-plane at the same time. You have a second curve applied to
the first curve. But these two curves cannot be added to create a
new curve that the body can follow as a whole. If the body were
free to follow both curves from the first dt, then the first
thing it would do is warp very badly. Very soon it would be
twisted beyond recognition. But real bodies are not free to warp
into any shape possible. They already have structure at many
levels, and this structure is rigid to one degree or another. So
if you try to apply a second circular motion to a real body, you
are applying a force that does not just lead to motion—you are
applying a force that is trying to break the body itself. It is
the molecular bonds themselves that are resisting you. The body
does not want to warp. This is why you can apply a second spin to
a liquid in circular motion. The liquid does not resist the
second orthogonal force. But your second force ends up destroying
the “body” of the circular motion, which in a liquid was just
a pattern anyway.
That
said, it is possible to have simultaneous x and y spins, but you
must apply the second spin to a center outside the object. What
I mean is that the electron must spin end over end, rather than
spin about the axis through its center. To
go back to the Earth example, you can see that we can easily
imagine the Earth hurtling end over end throughout space, since
this end over end motion would not affect its axis spin at all. A
gyroscope resists a 90o
force, but only because we
have fixed the center of the gyroscope relative to the force. A
gyroscope will not spin in two ways about its center. But if we
put the gyroscope in a spherical container, then we can rotate
the gyroscope around a point on the surface of the sphere. We can
do this even if the gyroscope is firmly attached to the
container. Take a spinning bicycle tire and extend the axle out
so that the diameter of the axle is equal to the diameter of the
wheel. Attach the ends of this axle firmly to a great sphere with
the same diameter, so that the wheel is inside the sphere. You
can now rotate that sphere about any point on the surface of the
sphere, without the internal motion causing precession. This is
because you are no longer attempting to cause two different
rotations about the same center. You have created a center just
beyond the influence of the first axis.
What is even
more interesting is that the circle of this new revolution now
has a center that is not stationary—it travels. And it travels
in a very interesting way. Let us say you have the Earth spinning
about the x-axis, and you give the center of the Earth a constant
velocity in the y-direction. Next, we add an end-over-end spin in
this same y-direction. Now, what sort of total curve would this
end over end spin create, for the center of the Earth? It
would create a wave.
[To see an
animation of this wave motion, you may take these links. The
first is a windows media file, the second requires Quicktime (and
is much faster to download). wave.wmv
4.5Mb. wave.mov
780kb. Expect to wait 30 seconds for the wmv file. Thanks to
Chris Wheeler for use of these files.]
Let that sink
in for a few seconds. Albert assumes that both angular momentums
are measured about the same center. Beyond that, he assumes that
the measured qualities or quantities don’t matter. He assumes
that angular momentum is conceptually equivalent to velocity or
position or any other parameter. He assumes that because that is
what all physicists have so far assumed. What matters for QED is
how these unanalyzed variables plug into equations. I have just
shown that the actual variables matter very much. The whole
explanation for QED lies in the real motions of these real
bodies, and the explanation is capable of being stated in simple,
direct terms, as I did it above. The two angular momentums not
only influence eachother in specific and distinct ways; the ways
they influence eachother provide the conceptual and physical
groundwork for QED—a groundwork that has so far been ignored.
But let us
return to Albert’s argument. He gives the electron color and
hardness, to simplify the analysis. The electron then has four
states: black, white, hard, soft. The physicist has equally
simple tools. He has a color box and a hardness box. If he feeds
in an unknown electron, the color box tells the physicist black
or white.
The hardness box tells him hard
or soft.
Now, if the
physicist feeds white or black electrons into a hardness box,
half trip the hard detector and half the soft. Likewise for hard
or soft electrons fed into a color box. This means, according to
Albert, that “the color of an electron apparently entails
nothing whatever about its hardness” or the reverse.
The problem
encountered by Albert’s physicist is that these two simple
detectors seem to work in strange ways, if you set them up in
combination. If the physicist sets up three boxes like this:
color box, hardness box, color box, the percentages at the end
are mystifying. The hardness box in the middle is set up so that
it captures only one emerging color, which Albert lets be white.
The white electrons travel to the middle hardness box, where half
of them make it through and go to the last box. The surprise is
that of those, only half are white when they come out. Our final
color box finds half of them are black. Wow. Albert and QED tell
us this is a big problem. It cannot be explained logically.
Albert says that his physicist tries everything. He builds his
boxes in a variety of ways, to make them more (or even less)
precise. It doesn’t matter. The same 50/50 split comes out at
the end.
This has been one of the central problems of
quantum physics from the very beginning. It has been a mystery
for at least 80 years. But the outcome is easily explainable once
you have my analysis above in hand, regarding the various spins.
Let’s say you have a sample of electrons and are going to
measure angular momentum in both zx and zy planes. If we have
four possible outcomes, then we assume that each momentum is
either clockwise or counterclockwise, relative to some observer.
Now, put yourself in the position of this observer and see what
happens. At the first moment, you look and you see that the
electron is rotating clockwise about its x-axis, with that axis
pointing straight at you. This means that the rotation is in the
zy-plane. In other words, you are looking at a little clock,
since it is moving relative to you just like the second hand on
the face of a clock. That clock face exists in the zy-plane. A
moment later the electron has rotated a half-turn, end over end
along the x-axis. This rotation is in the zx-plane, about a
traveling y-axis. After this half-turn, you look again at the
clock face. Its motion is the same, but it now appears
counterclockwise to you.
If that was
confusing, you can easily perform the above visualization with a
desk clock, provided of course that it is not digital. Hold the
clock in front of you. Its hands are turning clockwise, and they
represent the spin in the x-plane. Now give the entire clock a
spin in the y-plane, simply by turning it one half turn end over
end. If you do this you will now be looking at the back of the
clock. The second hand is now moving counterclockwise, relative
to you. It is that simple. That is all I am saying. The second
hand of the clock is spinning around an x-axis that is pointed
right at you. Then you spun the whole clock around a y-axis. Very
elementary, but it shows us that the x-spin of the electron must
be variable, if you measure it relative to an observer external
to the electron. If the electron has both x-spin and y-spin, then
the x-spin will be variable, measured by a stationary device.
Only an observer traveling with the electron would measure its
spin as consistently CW or CCW. The same thing applies in
reverse, of course. If you are measuring the other angular
momentum, then you get a periodic variance in the first one.
You could say
that the spin changes due to relativity, but that would actually
be over-complicating the situation. We don’t need any
transforms here, and the kind of simple relativity I have just
described was known long before Einstein. It is true that my
analysis used relativity to find a solution, but it is the
simplest, pre-Einstein sort of relativity. It is just to say that
an observer must pay attention to how the object he is measuring
is changing over time. A measuring device, whether it is an
eyeball or an electron detector, is a constant frame of
reference, and a spinning electron will show variance with regard
to that device at different times, as I have just shown. There is
nothing esoteric about it, although I suppose it is a subtle
thing to have to notice.
Once we apply
this to our measuring devices, whatever they are, we see that
this must affect our outcomes quite positively. Let us go inside
the first box. It was measuring color, so let us assign color to
the clock-face rotation. White is CW, black is CCW. The box finds
that some electrons are white and some black. To differentiate,
it must apply some field or force to them over some dt. Let us
imagine, to simplify, that the box feeds the electrons into a
chute, like cattle, and then puts them all through the same door.
This door is like the metal detector at the airport, except that
it takes a picture of the electron as it rushes through. It has a
very fast f-stop, an f-stop of dt. If the electron was CW at that
dt, then the box ejects it from the white door. If the electron
was CCW at that dt, then the box ejects it from the black door.
This is, in
fact, very much like the way detectors work. They don’t take
pictures, of course, but some sort of force or field separates
the white and black electrons. The field may not be limited to a
dt, but the first impression of the field is crucial. The
electrons are moving quite fast, and the time periods are
therefore quite small. The field doesn’t have time to snap a
bunch of pictures and start changing its mind.
What this all
means is that whiteness and blackness and softness and hardness
are not constants. Every electron is both black and white and
hard and soft, at different times. But it is all those things
only if you sum over some extended period of time. At each dt, it
is either hard or soft, black or white. It is not both at the
same time. At one measurement, it will be one or the other. Over
a series of measurements, it will be both.
This is the
subtlety that QED has never penetrated. It explains the above
problem like this: If you put electrons like those I have
described through a color box, the color box sees some of them as
black and some as white over the dt measured. But they are
actually not white or black as they come out—they remain
potentially both, depending on the point in the wave you measure.
If you measured the white ones coming out at a different point in
the wave motion, you would find them black, and vice versa. Now,
the color determination is repeatable, since a similar box will
catch the electrons in similar ways. All color boxes tend to
shute and channel electrons in the same way, so that the exiting
group is made coherent. A second color box must then read them
the same way as the first.
What happens
in the second box (the hardness box) solves the mystery. The
second box creates coherence in the second angular momentum. This
assures that other hardness boxes will find the same hardness.
But in creating this coherence, the second box re-randomizes the
first variable. Why does it do this? It does this because the
wavelength of the two angular momentums is different. If the
first wavelength was taken as R, for the radius of the electron,
then we have to take the second wavelength as 2R, for the
diameter. This is simply because the second wavelength is caused
by end over end rotation. If we cohere the end over end rotation,
this must split the measurement of the axial rotation. If we
cohere the axial rotation, this must split the measurement of the
end over end rotation. One is half the other, so you cannot
create coherence in both at the same time.
I can show
this with simple waves in two dimensions. Study the diagram
below. We have two opposite combinations of ½ and 1 waves. If
you synchronize the ½ waves, the 1 waves are off. If you
synchronize the 1 waves, then the ½ waves are off. You cannot
synchronize both. This, in essense, is what is happening in box
two. The hardness waves are being made coherent, so that the
color waves are being thrown out of synch. The third box then
reads them as ½ one and ½ the other.
You can see that I have simultaneously solved the problem
of superposition and the problem of the wave motion of quantum
particles. I did this simply by noticing that the second angular
momentum must be about a center that is just external to the
object. That is to say, the y-spin is end over end.
With the
hindsight this gives me, it seems shocking that this was not seen
earlier. The reason it was not seen is that Heisenberg and Bohr
convinced everyone early on that Quantum Mechanics could not be
explained with straightforward logic and simple visualizations.
No one has ever bothered to apply a little commonsense to the
physical situation. They were so sure that it couldn’t be done,
that they didn’t even try to tackle the problem on a visual or
mechanical basis. This predicament soon snowballed, since as more
and more great physicists looked at the problem and failed to
explain it, later physicists became more and more sure that it
couldn’t be solved. They did not want to waste their time
combing something that every genius from Bohr to Feynman had
already combed. That seemed not just foolish, but sacrilegious.
But the fact is that there has probably been no one since Bohr
that tried very hard to make classical sense of the problem.
Physicists who came right after Bohr took his word for it, and
contemporary physicists have reached the point where most don’t
even want a mechanical explanation of QED. The spooky paradoxes
are more fun. They make better copy.
You may now
go to my second
paper on superposition, to see a similar experiment solved
even more quickly and transparently. That experiment is the
famous one of two beam splitters and two mirrors. In that paper I
also offer three more diagrams, which may be helpful to many.
A related
problem is that of entanglement, which I
analyze and solve here.
More recently, I have blown
apart the CHSH Bell
tests, unveiling the terrible mathematical cheat at the heart
of these experiments. This leaves entanglement in tatters.
To
see how my solution destroys quantum nonlocality, you may go to
this recent paper,
which even gives you the new wavefunction equations—including
the new degrees of freedom I discovered above.
I think it is
obvious that the end over end spin in the y-direction can be
applied to other problems, including the
propagation of photons, the two-slit
experiment, and so on. In subsequent papers I will apply my
finding to the electron
and proton and to
a large list of mesons, to show that the same four stacked
spins can explain all quantum make-up and motion. I will also
have a lot more to say about other specific problems within QED
and QCD, and
their solution with straightforward logical analysis.
*Addendum,
Feb 2012: A close reader just asked me for clarification on the
spins here. He pointed out that the Earth has a wobble in its
spin. Isn't
that part of a second spin, since it isn't along the original
axis? If we continued the wobble, we could create a whole spin in
either direction. I
answered: Excellent question, and I will even add it to my
super.html paper, to clear up confusion. Let's look at your Earth
wobble, to get to the bottom of this. The Earth's wobble isn't
caused by two spins about two different axes, as in my example.
It is caused by a motion of the first axis. We let the Earth spin
on z, say, then we move z. Yes, we can actually spin z, moving
the north pole to the south, and I think that is what you are
getting at. We then have spins in two planes, which seems to
prove your point. We could then call the spin of z either x or y,
and it looks like I have been refuted. However, I have not been
refuted, since we are talking about different things. If you now
rename the spin of z as x-spin, your x-spin is not the same as
the x-spin I am outlawing. I have outlawed some x and y spin,
right? Well, I am outlawing the original x-spin, the one that is
the same sort of motion as the original z-spin. Which is a spin
about an axis. You have found a spin of
the axis, not a spin about
the axis. So my point holds.
That x-spin about an x-axis is still outlawed. In fact, your new
x-spin is the same as my end-over-end x-spin, since if we give
the Earth any linear motion, your x-spin will appear
end-over-end. North and south poles switching ends is
end-over-end, is it not?
He then
replied, Yes
that clears that up, but there is still the matter of the point
of spin. You say that the end-over-end spin needs to spin about a
point on the end of z. I have reminded you that we can spin z
about its center. What gives? And
I answered: I admit that it could be one or the other. Either way
creates what I would call an end-over-end spin. But my way allows
me to create my quantum spin equation, which answers a lot of
questions that have been in the shadows. So the argument for my
way is straight from data. The quanta could spin your way, but in
fact I don't think they do. The spin equation wouldn't fit data.
To be specific, if we let the z-axis spin about its center rather
than about one end, we don't get a doubling of the spin radius
with each added spin. We need that. See elecpro.html
for the spin equation I am talking about. As for the physical
reason quanta choose to stack spins that way, by spinning about a
point on the end of z, I don't see the answer yet. I suspect that
it is some analogue of the centrifugal force, and that the quick
first spin pushes following spins out to an "edge."
Could also have something to do with imperfect roundness of the
initial spin. They have supposedly just shown that the electron
is incredibly round, but nothing is perfectly round, I assume.
Any imperfection might cause later spins to be pushed outward
like this. If anyone has a better theory, he or she can email me
with it. I wouldn't say it is crucial, but it would be nice to
figure it out.
Update,
2013. I figured it out myself the next time I re-read this
paper. To understand why the photon's second spin spins around a
point on the original spin surface, we just have to look at the
cause of that second spin. I have shown previously it must be
caused by collision with another photon. The first photon stacks
a second spin on top of the first because it cannot spin any
faster on the first axis. It has reached a spin velocity of c,
and if it encounters a positive spin collision that would
increase its spin energy, it can stack that extra energy on only
by creating another spin. Well, since the point of collision is
on the outer surface, the photon naturally spins about that
point. The second spin must take as its new center that point of
collision.
If this paper
was useful to you in any way, please consider donating a dollar
(or more) to the SAVE THE ARTISTS FOUNDATION. This will allow me
to continue writing these "unpublishable" things. Don't
be confused by paying Melisa Smith--that is just one of my many
noms de plume. If you are a Paypal user, there is no fee;
so it might be worth your while to become one. Otherwise they
will rob us 33 cents for each transaction.
|